Ethical Issues in Longitudinal Research with At-Risk Children and Adolescents

Description

This case discusses issues of researcher obligations, the role of informed consent, developmental factors; and options of action available to researchers who discover that minors may be in jeopardy.

Body

Part 1

Part 2

Part 3

Part 4

Part 1

Dr. Judy Brewster, long interested in the effects of exposure to maladaptive environments on development, plans to design a study to examine resilience. Why are some individuals able to fend off the deleterious consequences associated with stressful environments and adverse circumstances, while others are not? What characteristics are associated with adaptation to such environments? To learn more about the characteristics associated with resilience to environmental insult, Judy will study fourth, sixth and eighth graders who have been exposed to violence within their communities.

Youths will be assessed at six-month intervals for a period of four years. Assessments will be conducted in school through group-administered written surveys and individual interviews of approximately one to two hours in length. The amount and frequency of exposure to community violence will be measured, as well as short- and long-term psychological (anxiety, depression, perception of social support), behavioral (academic achievement, risk engagement) and adaptational (psychological and behavioral coping) responses. Aside from assessment interviews, participants will have no contact with the researcher.

Ms. Rosen, the principal of a private parochial school, has agreed to allow her school to participate in the study. She is eager to assist her students and suggests that Judy begin at once. When Judy asks for advice on how to approach parents for their permission, the principal says that it is not necessary, as the school supports the study. Judy is unsure of how to respond. She recalls that ethical guidelines do not require parental consent to conduct evaluations of educational curricula; however, she is not evaluating a curriculum.

Discussion Questions

  1. What are Judy's responsibilities to the students, parents and Ms. Rosen, if any?
  2. What are the potential consequences of not obtaining consent for the students, parents, Ms. Rosen, and Judy, if any?
  3. Given the potential consequences, should Judy obtain parental consent?

Back to Top

Part 2

Judy explains to Ms. Rosen that her funding agency and university institutional review board require that she obtain parental consent. Ms. Rosen notes the difficulty in obtaining responses from every parent in the fourth, sixth, and eighth grades; she suggests that a letter be sent to parents advising them that the study will be conducted and asking them to return the permission form if they do not want their child to participate.

Discussion Questions

  1. How well does this method of consent protect the autonomy rights of the students?
  2. What about the parents?
  3. Are there alternative methods of obtaining consent? What are the advantages and disadvantages of each?
  4. How should Judy obtain parental consent?

Back to Top

Part 3

Approximately two years into her study, Judy notices two distinct patterns of adaptation. Some of the children exhibit signs of distress, anxiety and depression, and report that they have begun to engage in multiple risk behaviors such as substance use, delinquency, violence and sexual promiscuity. Other children show no signs of distress, or have outgrown and discontinued such behaviors. Judy is concerned about the acting-out youth, but she notes that many children have engaged in such behaviors and later discontinued engagement.

Discussion Questions

  1. What are Judy's responsibilities to the participants in her study? How do they differ from her responsibilities to the parents? the university? the funding agency?
  2. Does Judy have the same obligations and responsibilities to fourth graders as sixth graders? What about eighth graders?
  3. What options of action are available to Judy?
  4. How well do each of these options protect the rights of the students? the parents?

Back to Top

Part 4

After extensive discussion with colleagues, Judy decides that she has four options available. She may: 1) do nothing and maintain confidentiality, as initially promised; 2) report excessive risk engagement to parents; 3) provide students with referral information so that they may obtain help; or 4) intervene. However, reporting, intervening or providing referral information may defeat the purpose of her study: to examine long-term effects of exposure to community violence in natural conditions.

Judy is not clinically trained; she is not competent to diagnose or treat distressed participants. She is, however, competent to teach students adaptive skills such as anger management and conflict resolution, which have been shown to have limited success in altering behavior. However, intervening may invalidate her results. After deliberation, Judy decides to do nothing to protect the validity of her study.

Discussion Questions

  1. Does maintaining confidentiality fulfill Judy's ethical obligations and responsibilities to her participants, parents, university and funders? Why or why not?
  2. Was Judy's decision ethical? Why or why not?
Notes

Used with permission of Association for Practical and Professional Ethics. Case drawn from Research Ethics: Fifteen Cases and Commentaries, Volume One, Brian Schrag, Ed., February 1997.

Citation
. . Ethical Issues in Longitudinal Research with At-Risk Children and Adolescents. Online Ethics Center. DOI:. https://onlineethics.org/cases/graduate-research-ethics-cases-and-commentaries-volume-1-1997/ethical-issues-longitudinal.

Scope and nature of the study

Informed consent and assent

Judy's moral obligation for subjects' welfare

Three claims for excusing an obligation for subjects' welfare

Privacy, confidentiality and parental responsibility

Scope and nature of the study

Judy proposes to study fourth, sixth and eighth graders who have been "exposed to violence in their community." The scope and nature of the study are important in thinking about the ethical considerations and implications of the study. The children range widely in age and maturity, and they will presumably mature considerably by the end of the four-year study. The subjects' capacity for informed consent and their concern for confidentiality and privacy may vary initially and may change over the course of the study.

What does the category of "community violence" include? Does it include domestic violence within their own nuclear families? Does it exclude domestic violence within the nuclear family, but include violence in the extended family and all other exposures to violence in their community? Does it exclude all family violence (nuclear and extended) but include all other violence in their immediate community? Does the study propose to investigate violence suffered directly by students at the hands of family, neighbors and strangers; does it propose to study the impact of merely observing or being aware of such violence; or will it attempt all of the above?

Through individual interviews and group-administered surveys, the study proposes to measure the subjects' amount and frequency of exposure to community violence as well as their psychological, behavioral and adaptational responses to violence. If the study includes experiences of violence in the nuclear or extended family, subjects may be probed about experiences of child abuse and other violence by family members, among other things. If it focuses only on violence witnessed by the students, including the family setting, the investigator may solicit information from subjects that may include information about domestic abuse in their families. In either case, this probing certainly constitutes invasion of privacy and has implications for obtaining informed consent from the parents or appropriate family members. Will parents clearly understand that their children's participation in the study may result in invasion of the family's privacy?

If the study focuses only on the student's direct involvement in violence outside the family, the investigator may solicit incidents of violence the subject has committed or which were committed against the subject. At the extreme, that may involve admitting to participation in gang activity, or criminal activity or being the victim of sexual assault. If the study focuses only on the student's awareness of violence in the community, students may admit witnessing violent criminal behavior. These questions make the students extremely vulnerable and have serious implications for the process of obtaining informed consent from both parents and students as well as for level of confidentiality maintained in the study.

Will students understand that they may reveal such information as subjects? Will they be clear about the degree of confidentiality maintained? Will parents expect to be informed of the subjects' behavior?

The study solicits students' psychological responses (depression, suicidal thoughts), behavioral responses (drinking) and their adaptational responses (delinquency and sexual promiscuity). These questions raise all sorts of issues of privacy, confidentiality, informed consent and researcher's responsibilities for the welfare of subjects. Judy may become aware of many instances of dangerous and even illegal behavior that she is legally required to report. Will students understand that they may reveal such information during the study? Will they expect it to be kept confidential? Will parents expect this information? Will the parents expect Judy's first concern to be the welfare of her subjects? Will parents assume Judy has the expertise needed to act for their child's welfare if she discovers the child is engaged in risky behavior? Does Judy have an obligation to intervene on behalf of the subjects even if that means weakening or ruining the study? Is Judy's paramount obligation not to the subjects' welfare but to carry out the research, in the best manner possible?

Judy can anticipate many of these issues before the protocol is designed. It may be possible to practice "preventive ethics" and design the protocol to avoid some of the ethical issues that may otherwise develop as the study progresses.

Back to Top

Informed consent and assent

This research will be highly invasive of the privacy of the children and may be equally invasive of the privacy of other family members. The study may also place the subjects at considerable risk if their confidences about sensitive matters are violated. These facts alone are one argument for requiring the child's assent as well as the family's permission. The research is not likely to provide any direct benefit to either the children or their families, although it is possible that it will yield generalized knowledge of benefit to all children. In such circumstances, federal guidelines require that the researchers solicit the "assent" of minor children to participate in research if the children are capable of assent. (Title 45, Code of Federal Regulations 46.408 (a) 1991) Parental or guardian permission is also required. (45 CFR 46.408 (b) 1991) In this case, the quality of the subjects' assent and of the parents' permission is an extremely important moral issue.

The notion of assent of minors and how it relates to informed consent is unclear. (Macklin, 1992, 90) Fourth graders are not adults. They may not be capable of fully appreciating the limitations of the trust they should place in the researcher. They may not understand the risks when confidences are breached. They may underestimate how their attitude toward invasion of privacy may change as they mature. They may not be capable of balancing all these considerations as well as an adult, who will have greater experience and maturity. (See Macklin, 1992, 101, on understanding privacy.) Nevertheless, even fourth graders, and clearly sixth and eighth graders, are capable of understanding a great deal if information is presented appropriately. (Thompson, 1992, 61) It is morally significant that their assent be sought only after they receive that information.

The variability of ages, developing maturity levels and the length of the study all complicate the assent issue. Some subjects will enter the study as fourth graders; others will end the study as juniors or seniors in high school. Children become much more sensitive to privacy as they move into adolescence. (Thompson, 1992) Subjects may assent to invasions of privacy as fourth graders that they would not assent to as eighth graders. The law recognizes the capacity of young adolescents to make adult-like decisions. In some states, minors can legally self-refer themselves for medical treatment for venereal diseases, alcoholism, contraceptives and abortions without the knowledge or consent of their parents. (Brooks-Gunn, 1994, 116; Rogers et. al., 1994, 3)

Children in this study have a right to understand what they are assenting to. Judy should provide the subjects with at least the following age-appropriate information: 1) An explanation of the nature and purpose of the research and the nature and role of the researcher. The children should understand that the research activity is not intended to benefit them and that the researcher's primary concern is not to benefit them as subjects. This point is particularly important for younger children. They may tend to think that an authority figure who is called doctor (Ph.D.) and meets with them in the school setting has a role akin to their family physician or a teacher and is acting in their best interests. 2) A clear understanding of the sorts of information that they will be asked to share. 3) A clear understanding that they have a right to refuse to answer any of the questions raised in the study. 4) A clear understanding of the level of confidentiality of the information they share and the limits of that confidentiality. They should clearly understand the circumstances, if any, in which Judy will break their confidences and with whom she might share that information, including parents, health officials or legal authorities. 5) A clear indication that they can drop out of the study at any point. 6) Since the maturation levels of the subjects may change significantly over four years, Judy should consider the provision that the subjects' assent will be renegotiated at the beginning of each year of the study.

Parents have a right to know what they are giving permission for. A careful procedure for informing the parents is required. 1) Judy should take pains to ensure that parents understands that the research activity is not intended for the therapeutic benefit of their children. 2) Judy should tell parents specifically the sorts of information she will collect from the children and with whom it might be shared. Parents should be clear about the kinds of information Judy is legally required to report to authorities, such as suspected child abuse. 3) Parents should understand what, if any, confidential information gained from their child Judy will or will not share with the parents about the child. In particular, parents should be clear how Judy will deal with information about serious psychological symptoms or risky behavior manifested by their child or whether she will disclose information about the child's self-referrals. If such information is not shared with the parents, can the parents expect that Judy will seek interventions on behalf of the child, where appropriate?

All of this implies that Judy must plan for a sophisticated process of informing potential subjects and their parents before obtaining assent and permission. Merely sending out permission slips to be signed and returned will not be sufficient. Judy needs to plan a more elaborate method of informing potential subjects and their parents in the consent process. She may also need to contact a much wider pool of potential subjects than otherwise anticipated. It is likely that when parents understand what she will be doing and students are clear about their rights to withdraw from the research, more parents will refuse to give their permission, and more subjects will withdraw or may be dropped during the course of the research.

We have argued that Judy has a moral obligation to make clear to both prospective subjects and their parents exactly what they can expect from Judy should she become aware that their child is in a high-risk situations. What exactly should she be prepared to do in such situations?

Back to Top

Judy's moral obligation for subjects' welfare

1. The case for doing nothing

Judy may argue on three grounds that she has no moral obligation to do anything to safeguard the welfare of her subjects during the research. Judy's research simply involves watching what would have happened to these children anyway, whether or not she was conducting the research; her study is a kind of natural laboratory. Whether or not Judy conducts the research, the same children would have engaged in the same risky behavior in exactly the same way, without their parents' knowledge. She has an obligation not to harm subjects but she is not causing any harm to the subjects.

If she intervenes, she may not be able to maintain the integrity of her research and research program. The long-term benefits of the study would outweigh anything that might happen to subjects because she did not intervene.

Suppose that Judy obtains permission from parents for their child to participate in the study with the clear understanding that should Judy discover that their child is engaging in high risk behavior, she will not act on that information in any way, unless required by law. The child also assents. Judy will not inform parents, she will not take steps to assist the child, even if she knows that she is the sole adult who is aware that the child is in a threatening situation or is engaging in self-destructive activity that presents a clear and present danger to the child (anorexic behavior, heavy drinking, drugs, sexual promiscuity or gang activity). Judy will simply carry on her research.

Judy may take the position that she is not morally obligated to do anything, given the fact that she is doing no harm to the children, that she is armed with parental permission and child assent to a noninterventionist policy on her part, and that, given such a policy, she will maximize benefits by conducting the best study possible. She has no obligation to intervene on behalf of children at risk; all things considered, she has an obligation to refrain from intervening in order to maximize benefits. She is satisfying the principle of beneficence as articulated in the Belmont Report, which provides ethical guideline for research on human subjects. (National Commission, 1979)

The first part of this argument parallels the argument given by researchers in the Tuskegee syphilis experiment (Jones, 1993). Unlike Judy's project, those adult subjects had not given their informed and voluntary consent to be experimental subjects. Nevertheless, Judy's position is subject to some of the same criticisms.

2. The case for doing something

To see why Judy is mistaken, consider for a moment how we would define the moral obligations of ordinary persons (who are not researchers) in a somewhat parallel situation. Imagine that Judy is not a researcher but an ordinary citizen who walks through a park and notices a fourth grader she knows, sitting alone, playing Russian roulette with a gun. She realizes that she is the only adult in the area aware of the child's activity, and yet she takes no action but walks on by. Normally, we would say Citizen Judy has an obligation to intervene to stop the child from harming himself, if she can do so at minimal risk to herself.

On what moral grounds would we make such a claim? The principle of beneficence is one moral principle that we recognize as applicable to all persons. That principle states that we all have an obligation to promote the good and to prevent or avoid doing harm.

Notice that an obligation to maximize benefit presupposes this obligation. Unless we already have an obligation to promote the good and avoid harm, we could not have an obligation to maximize the good. The obligation to promote good and avoid harm can actually be regarded as a set of prima facie obligations to: 1) avoid doing harm, 2) prevent harm, 3) remove harm and 4) promote good. Furthermore, these obligations are listed in their order of stringency. The stringency has in part to do with the fact that it takes less effort avoid doing harm than it does to prevent a harm, to remove a harm or to do good. I should not push children off the end of a pier; I have a less stringent obligation to buy them an ice cream cone. If we can prevent or remove a harm at little risk or cost to ourselves, we have an obligation to do so. If I am standing on the pier and notice that a child has fallen into the water, and if I can save it by throwing a lifeline, I have a moral obligation to do so. The implication of this articulation of the principle for Citizen Judy is that she not only has an obligation to avoid harming the child, she also has an obligation to try to prevent the harm about to happen, if she can do so at minimal risk. (Frankena, 1973, 45-47)

In her research, Judy may become aware that one of her subjects is engaging in risky behavior such as contemplating suicide, practicing unprotected sex, engaging in heavy drinking, abusing drugs or beginning to run with a gang. Suppose that Judy can, at minimal risk to herself, do something to prevent the child from coming to harm but decides to do nothing about it. Unless Judy can show how her status as a researcher excuses her from this obligation, she is mistaken in thinking she can simply do nothing. One might argue that the difference is that Judy is a scientist and, as such, she has professional moral obligations that override the obligation of ordinary morality to prevent harm to another. Judy might give three different claims to support that position.

Back to Top

Three claims for excusing an obligation for subjects' welfare

1. The obligation to welfare is overridden by the obligation to do research.

Judy might argue that scientists have a professional obligation -- and indeed an overriding obligation -- to conduct their research in the most rigorous and scientifically sound manner possible. The best contribution a scientist can make to the general welfare is a contribution to the general knowledge, which will allow effective social policy. In a conflict of general and professional moral obligations, professional obligations are trump. In a research project designed to study the impact of violence in children, one is likely to encounter a higher incidence of children with risky behavior. To intervene to help a subject would threaten the integrity of the research project and thus society might lose the tremendous benefit of such research for children everywhere. Hence Judy ought not intervene.

However, a mere conflict of professional obligations with the obligations of ordinary morality does not excuse scientists from the obligations of ordinary morality. Simply being engaged in scientific activity does not excuse scientists, for example, from prima facie obligations not to steal, to tell the truth or to come to the aid of a person in distress even if doing so interferes with their scientific activity or jeopardizes the results of a particular research project. Professional moral obligations presuppose general moral obligations; they are not independent of them. (Bayles, 1989, Chapter 2)

2. The obligation to welfare is waived by parental permission.

Judy cannot be excused from obligations of ordinary morality in this case by the permission of parents and child. Recall the case of the child playing Russian roulette. Suppose, for some bizarre reason, the parent had given Judy permission to ignore their child in the event she ever saw the child playing Russian roulette. We would not say Judy was absolved from a moral responsibility to act simply because the parent gave her permission. (We would be more inclined to say that the parent was acting irresponsibly.) Would it make any difference if, as a researcher, Judy had obtained similar permission from the parent?

The Belmont Report articulates two principles guiding human research that are relevant here. First is the principle of treating subjects with the respect due humans: One must never treat humans solely as a means to one's own ends. Suppose that Judy, in virtue of her research, is the sole adult who is aware that a child is entertaining the possibility of suicide. She knows that if she does not act, no one will. If Judy takes no action because that would interfere with the research program, then she is treating the child solely as a means to her own ends and is violating the principle of respect for persons.

The second ethical principle is that of beneficence. As the Belmont Report puts it, the principle of beneficence is a twofold obligation:

Two general rules have been formulated as complimentary expressions of beneficent actions in this sense: (1) do not harm and (2) maximize possible benefits and minimize possible harms.

I have already indicated that I do not think this articulation of the principle of beneficence is adequate because the claim that we have an obligation to maximize possible benefits already presupposes that we have a prior and more stringent obligation to do good and avoid evil. Judy has a stronger prima facie obligation to prevent harm to her subject than she has to maximize benefits.

3. The welfare obligation is overridden by the obligation of confidentiality.

Suppose Judy promises the subjects that she will never violate their confidence and never reveal to anyone, including parents, anything the subjects tell her. Normally we would say we have an obligation to maintain such a confidence because we have promised to do so. It is not clear on what grounds one would argue that keeping promises and confidentiality always trumps all other moral considerations, however. There may be situations in which other moral considerations outweigh an obligation to keep a promise -- for example, situations that threaten the life of the person promised. There are no compelling moral grounds for asserting that keeping confidences is always the highest moral obligation. It is also the case that Judy has legal obligations to report certain kinds of criminal behavior such as suspected child abuse. She should not make promises she knows she cannot keep.

I have argued that one must conclude that Judy cannot morally justify the position that she should never intervene by appealing to the mere fact that she is a researcher. If Judy's research proposal can reasonably be expected to give her knowledge that a child subject's health or welfare is seriously threatened and the situation requires immediate intervention, she must recognize that she has a prima facie obligation to take some action in some of these circumstances. She cannot morally defend a position of never doing anything. It is not clear that either the federal guidelines or the Belmont Report would reach this conclusion, but other standards do. The Society for Research in Child Development asserts:

When, in the course of research , information comes to the investigator's attention that may jeopardize the child's well-being, the investigator has the responsibility to discuss the information with the parents, guardians or with those expert in the field in order that they may arrange the necessary assistance for the child. (SRCD, 1993, 339)

Back to Top

Specifying an obligation to act.

It behooves Judy to take this moral responsibility into account as she designs, seeks funding for and carries out her research. She should make clear to the funding agent, and to parents and subjects, what interventions she is prepared to undertake on behalf of the children, even if those steps impair the quality of the research. However, the fact that Judy has an obligation to take some action to prevent harm to subjects, does not establish what action she ought to take.

There are certain parameters on what Judy should and should not do. 1) Judy has a legal obligation to report to appropriate authorities certain things such as suspected child abuse. (Some have argued that the specific issue of reporting suspected child abuse is a morally problematic requirement since less than half of all reported cases are substantiated and reporting suspected abuse when it has not happened may well do serious harm to both child and parents. [ Scott-Jones, 1994, 101-103]) 2) If Judy has some obligation to protect the welfare of the child, she should not report to parents things that may result in the parents harming the child. Notifying parents may only make things worse (for example, if there is a clear case of child abuse by a parent). 3) It is reasonable to argue that Judy should not report to parents the fact that their child has referred herself to agencies to seek medical help in those instances in which the law allows the child to do so without the knowledge or consent of parents. (Scarr, 1994, 153). Judy has an obligation to make clear in the process of obtaining informed consent from parents and subjects that she will operate within these parameters.

If we assume that Judy, parents and subjects all understand she will act within these three parameters, a large gray area remains of risky behavior of subjects she may uncover in the course of her research. Should she ever notify the parents about such activity, encourage students to refer themselves for help, or initiate action on behalf of the subjects?

Privacy, confidentiality and parental responsibility

A central issue here involves conflicts between maintaining the confidentiality and privacy of child subjects, interfering with the responsibilities of parents, protecting the subjects' welfare and maintaining a viable research program.

As a moral agent, Judy has a prima facie obligation to maintain her subjects' privacy. All persons, including children, have a right to privacy, and can be wronged when it is violated. Research suggests that children value privacy, even at a young age. (Melton, 1992) As children mature, privacy is increasingly important as an indicator of independence and self esteem; it is necessarily paralleled by a reduction of parents' right of control over the child. (Macklin, 1992, 103; Melton, 1992) Notice that one can morally wrong a person by invading his or her privacy whether or not confidentiality is involved. Violating confidences is only one way of invading privacy.

If Judy has promised the children to keep certain information from the study strictly confidential, then breaking that confidence both invades their privacy and violates a promise. An obligation to preserve the subject child's confidentiality is especially strong if breaking that confidence to parents or others is likely to result in harm to the interests of the subject.

As a scientist, Judy may be concerned that breaking confidentiality may also unravel the study. Once one child's confidence has been broken, that child is unlikely to be candid and may have to be dropped from the study. As other children learn that their information is not kept confidential, they may wish to drop out of the study. If children know in advance that their confidences may be breached, they may not agree to do the study.

Judy might consider informing subjects and parents that, subject to the parameters already identified, she will keep everything else she learns about the subject absolutely confidential. But she might conceal from them her intention to break a confidence, if extreme circumstances warrant it. This plan may initially reassure subjects of confidentiality and thus increase the likelihood that they will agree to participate, and it includes a plan for protecting the subjects' welfare or informing parents, if necessary.

This strategy is not a good idea. If Judy knows from the beginning that this is what she intends to do, then she is engaging in a deceptive practice that undercuts the moral legitimacy of the subjects' assent. If she breaks confidences more than once, the word may get around that Judy does not maintain the confidences she said she would maintain, and the study may unravel anyway. It would be better to tell all parties from the beginning that if Judy believes that the subject is in clear and present danger, she may break confidences and tell the parents or take other action.

This discussion has focused on preserving the subjects' privacy and confidentiality, maintaining the integrity of the study and meeting the researcher's obligation to protect the subjects' welfare. Parents' authority and responsibility to care for their children must also be considered. What claim do parents have to information about their child's risky behavior?

Return to the case of Citizen Judy walking by the fourth grader who is playing Russian roulette. Suppose she intervenes and stops the child from playing Russian roulette and then notices that his family, whom she also knows, is not far away and is unaware of what has just transpired. Instead of notifying the family, Judy says nothing to them and whisks the child off to see a counselor without the family's knowledge. She recognizes that she has an obligation to do something for the child's welfare but maintains that her obligation does not include notifying of the parents since that might violate the child's privacy rights.

Normally we would say that Citizen Judy has an obligation to make the family aware of the event because of the presumption that it is the family's business and responsibility to care for their children; that includes keeping children from harming themselves. Parents may well claim that the family is best able to judge what is in the child's best interests in these situations. It is also the family that will have to deal with the situation and the consequences of the child's action.

We have already indicated Citizen Judy may be right to avoid notifying the parents if she has good reason to think the parents would make the situation even more dangerous for the child. That important set of circumstances aside, why should Judy assume that the child's best interest is served by substituting her judgment for that of the family? Why should she assume that maintaining the child's privacy rights is preferable to notifying the family and allowing their judgment to take over?

There is something wrong with Citizen Judy assuming the role of protector of the child because it is precisely the responsibility of parents to care for and nurture their own children and to keep them from harming themselves. Parents have a prima facie claim to be informed when their children are engaged in harmful activity even if that notification is at the cost of the child's privacy, confidentiality and self-determination. Parents' claims may diminish with the maturity of the child, but the burden of proof ought to be on those who would ignore that prima facie claim. Even John Stuart Mill, one of the most ardent defenders of individual rights and the private right to private damage, recognized the limitations on the notion of self-determination as applied to children:

Over himself and over his own body and mind, the individual is sovereign. it is perhaps hardly necessary to say that this doctrine is meant to apply only to humans being in the maturity of their faculties. We are not speaking of children or young persons below the age which the law may fix as that of manhood or womanhood. Those who are in a state that requires being taken care of by others, must be protected from themselves as well as against external injury. (Mill, 1961, 263)

Judy might argue that if she notices any risky behavior of such a serious nature, either the parents are already aware of it or, if they are not, that is evidence that they are not competent to deal with the problem. Therefore it is not in the child's best interest to notify the parents, and the parents do not have a right to be informed, at least not until other appropriate steps are taken. Once Citizen Judy is aware of a subject's risky behavior, she might counsel the child, offer to refer the child to competent professionals, or inform or consult with appropriate care givers or authorities. All of these options would address the child's welfare but preserve the child's privacy and confidentiality from their parents. Only at some later date, if ever, would the parents be notified.

The rationale for this approach, some have argued, presupposes a problematic view of the family and the relation of children's interests to the family and to parental and authority and responsibilities (Brown, 1982; Steinfels, 1982; Macklin, 1982). In particular the child is simply one member of an aggregate of individuals (family) bent on self-development and self-fulfillment. The interests of parents and children may conflict. Consequently, parents have only limited capacity to speak for the child's interests in the best of circumstances, and it is reasonable to think that a skilled professional may do as well as the parent. Hence the moral authority of parents over their children and the right to have information about their children is limited. It would not be wrong for an outsider to intervene to serve as interpreter, spokesman and protector of the child's interests. Resolving this issue is beyond the scope of this commentary. Notice that Citizen Judy knows some very important information about the child that the parents do not have. That fact gives her the power to prevent parents from carrying out their obligation to protect their child from harming himself.

Does the situation change if Judy is not just an ordinary citizen but a researcher? If she has this knowledge about the child, it is not by happenstance. Rather, it is because she is carrying on research with the parents' permission. What would good and reasonable parents agree to in such research? Would they expect a researcher to notify them if their child were engaged in risky behavior? They may expect it, precisely because they take seriously their responsibility to protect their children from harming themselves. Would they agree to having their children participate in an experiment if they knew such information would not be shared with them?

If Judy has a moral obligation to act on behalf of the welfare of the child, and if parents waive a claim to be informed of risky behavior, that constitutes ceding decision-making power to Judy to initiate treatment for the child. Would good and reasonable parents agree to that?

Parents might reason that any information about their child's risky behavior acquired by the researcher is information the parents would not have received otherwise. Parents might be willing to have a researcher act for the benefit of the child on the grounds that getting help for their child in this way is better than no help at all.

This case raises very complex issues for designing a protocol that is ethical and still allows the possibility of good research. Judy faces issues in Part 4 that could be avoided by full disclosure to prospective subjects and their parents of the degree to which she will share information of risky behavior with parents. It is perhaps an open question if enough subjects and parents will agree to participate to make the study possible, once they have been so informed. What Judy cannot do is to cut any of these corners in order to conduct the research.

Back to Top

References

  • Bayles, Michael D. Professional Ethics. 2d ed. Belmont: Wadsworth, 1989, pp.17-31.
  • Brooks-Gunn, J., and Rotheram-Borus, M. J. "Rights to Privacy In Research: Adolescents Versus Parents," Ethics and Behavior 4 (2, 1994): 109-121.
  • Brown, P. "Human Independence and Parental Proxy." In Willard Gaylin and Ruth Macklin, eds. Who Speaks for the Child? New York: The Hastings Center, 1982.
  • Department of Health and Human Services. "Protection of Human Subjects." Code of Federal Regulations, Title 45, Part 46 revised, 1991.
  • Frankena, William. Ethics. Englewood Cliffs: Prentice Hall, 1973, pp. 45-48.
  • Jones, James H. Bad Blood: The Tuskegee Syphilis Experiment, 2d ed. New York: The Free Press, 1993.
  • Macklin, Ruth. "Autonomy, Beneficence and Child Development: An Ethical Analysis." In B. Stanley and J. Seiber, eds. Social Science Research on Children and Adolescents: Ethical Issues. Newbury Park, Calif.: Sage, 1992, pp.88-105.
  • Macklin, Ruth. "Return to the Best Interests for the Child." In Willard Gaylin and Ruth Macklin, eds. Who Speaks for the Child. New York: The Hastings Center, 1982.
  • Mill, John Stuart. "On Liberty" The Essential Works of John Stuart Mill. New York: Bantam Books, 1961.
  • Melton, Gary B. "Respecting Boundaries: Minors, Privacy and Behavioral Research." In B. Stanley and J. Seiber, eds. Social Science Research on Children and Adolescents: Ethical Issues. Newbury Park, Calif.: Sage, 1992, pp. 65-88.
  • National Commission for the Protection of Human Subjects of Biomedical and Behavioral Research. The Belmont Report: Ethical Principles and Guidelines for the Protection of Human Subjects of Research. Washington, D.C.: Government Printing Office, 1979.
  • Rogers, A. S.; D'Angelo, L.; Futterman, D. "Guidelines for Adolescent Participation in Research: Current Realities and Possible Solutions." IRB: A Review of Human Subjects Research 16 (4, 1994): 1-6.
  • Scarr, S. "Ethical Problems in Research on Risky Behaviors and Risky Populations" Ethics and Behavior 4 (2,1994): 147-155
  • Scott-Jones, D. "Ethical Issues in Reporting and Referring in Research With Low-Income Minority Children." Ethics and Behavior 4 (2,1994): 97-108.
  • Society for Research in Child Development. " Ethical Standards for Research With Children." In Directory of Members, 1993, pp. 337-339.
  • Steinfels, M. "Children's Rights, Parental Rights, Family Privacy and Autonomy" In Who Speaks for the Child? Willard Gaylin and Ruth Macklin, eds. New York: The Hastings Center, 1982.
  • Thompson, Ross. "Developmental Changes in Research Risk and Benefit: A Changing Calculus of Concern." In B. Stanley and J. Seiber eds. Social Science Research on Children and Adolescents: Ethical Issues. Newbury Park, Calif.: Sage, 1992, pp. 31-65.
  • U. S. Department of Health and Human Services. "Protection of Human Subjects." Code of Federal Regulations Title 45, Part 46 (rev. 1991).
  • Weithorn, L. (1983) "Children's Capacities to Decide to Participate in Research." IRB: A Review of Human Subjects Research 5 (2): 1-5.

Author: Brian Schrag, Association for Practical and Professional Ethics.

Although many considerations are involved in this case, four broad areas deserve comment: researcher obligations, the role of informed consent, developmental factors; and options of action available to researchers who discover that minors may be in jeopardy.

1. Researcher Obligations

Who are the interested parties? What are Judy's responsibilities to each? How might each conflict?

The interested parties include the students, parents, Ms. Rosen and Judy's funders. She holds different responsibilities to each party, which, at times, conflict. For example, Judy promises the students that she will keep their responses secret and will not disclose their information to anyone. The students trust Judy not to violate that promise.

On the other hand, parents give permission for their children to participate in research with the understanding that Judy will act to maximize potential benefits and will not cause harm to the children, in accordance with the principles of beneficence and nonmaleficence (National Commission, 1979). In designing her research protocol and consent procedures, it is imperative that Judy consider parental expectations. Parents of at-risk youth may view any contact with professionals as a means of gaining assistance for their children and may erroneously assume that benefit will come from participation; that assumption may influence parental consent (Fisher, 1993; Thompson, 1992). In addition, parents may believe that the researcher's responsibility to act in the interests of the youth requires the researcher to disclose information that suggests that a student is in jeopardy; however, research protocols do not always correspond to this belief. Although Judy is obligated to keep the participants in her study from foreseeable harm, the parents may also feel that she is obligated to inform them of potential dangers to the students (i.e., excessive engagement in risky behavior).

Ms. Rosen, as a principal or school administrator, seeks information that will help the school as a whole and assist her in making administrative decisions. She seeks some disclosure of information; however, unlike the parents, she does not require unique identifiers or student names.

Judy is obligated by her sense of scientific integrity to conduct sound research. However, Judy's proposal is supported by grants; she is obligated by more than scientific virtue to conduct the best study possible. Her grant sources require her to conduct a thorough, scientifically valid study that, ideally, finds significant results.

It is apparent that Judy's obligations to these parties conflict. In sum, Judy is obligated to protect confidentiality, as she promised the students, as well as to protect them from harm. Appropriately, parents trust her to act in the best interests of the youth and may expect good, or at least no harm, to come from the interaction. Parents may also assume that information pertinent to youths' welfare will be fully disclosed; here, Judy's responsibilities to parents may conflict with her promise to her participants. In addition, Judy's relationship with funders obligates her to obtain meaningful, valid results. Providing a referral or intervention for a child or teen in jeopardy may damage the validity of Judy's study, compromising her obligation to her funders.

Back to Top

2. The Role of Informed Consent

What is informed consent?

The requirement of informed consent for participation in research was first iterated in the Nuremberg Code (1949), following the Nazi atrocities in World War II. Informed consent is a means of protecting participant autonomy and providing protection for those with diminished autonomy, an extension of the ethical principle of respect for persons (National Commission, 1979). The provision of consent to participate in research implies that an individual has made a voluntary and informed decision to participate. That is, the decision to participate must be made by a person with the rational as well legal capacity to decide; the person must be adequately informed; and the decision must not be coerced.

The following information must be disclosed to the participant: an explanation of the purpose of the research, anticipated duration of involvement; the procedures involved; potential risks, discomforts, benefits, alternatives; assurances of confidentiality; and identification of whom to contact with questions (ß46.116; Department of Health and Human Services [DHHS], 1991). In addition, participants must understand that participation is voluntary and that refusal will not penalize them in any way and will not result in a loss of benefits (ß46.116). In research on minors, parents' or guardians' permission is required, as well as the child's assent. In other words, both parent and child must be informed of the voluntariness, risks and benefits of participation in a way that is appropriate to the individual's developmental and educational level (ß46.408). Although parents must provide permission, minors have absolute veto power (Tymchuk, 1992).

When is informed consent required, and how may it be sought?

Federal guidelines (ß46.101; DHHS, 1991) stipulate that all research involving human subjects requires informed consent from participants. The exception is research examining normal educational practices such as a comparison of the effectiveness of instructional methods or curriculum techniques. As Judy's research does not fall under the umbrella of educational research, she is not exempt from consent requirements.

Parental consent for minors' participation in research may be sought either actively, whereby parents and guardians are informed of the proposed research procedures and must respond in order for their child to participate, or passively, whereby parents are sent letters describing the research and are to respond only if they do not want their child to participate. It has been argued that passive consent does not respect parental autonomy in that the researcher can never be certain that the parent received the information or that failure to respond reflects an informed agreement to allow the child to participate (Fisher, 1993). Parental permission may be differentiated from child assent, which refers to the child's agreement to participate and protects his or her developing autonomy (Tymchuk, 1992); both permission and assent are necessary in research with minors.

How may the rights of parents and minors conflict?

As the principle of respect for persons requires autonomous decisions about whether to engage in treatment (National Commission, 1979), the requirement of parental permission until age 18 presumes that youth need parental protection because they are not autonomous, or able to make rational decisions on their own. Youths' lack of autonomy may be challenged on two grounds: 1) parents do not always act in the best interests of their children, as is evident in cases of child abuse; and 2) many adolescents are cognitively able to make reasoned decisions (Brooks-Gunn and Rotheram-Borus, 1994). The developmental literature provides a wealth of information about the cognitive capacities of adolescents to consent. Minors below the age of 11 generally do not have the intellectual ability and volition to give informed, voluntary and rational consent; by mid-adolescence, however, teens are able to consider treatment alternatives, risks and benefits, and provide rational and voluntary consent comparable to that of adults (Grisso and Vierling, 1978; Weithorn, 1983; Weithorn and Campbell, 1982).

Back to Top

4. Developmental Factors

How important are developmental factors in decision making? Does Judy's responsibility vary with the age of the participants?

The developmental status of the participants must be carefully considered at least twice in the research plan: first, when planning research and weighing minor vulnerabilities with proposed research protocols; and second, when making decisions about reporting and referring minors who may be in need of assistance. When planning research with children and youth, an investigator's assumptions about development and vulnerability are crucial to the decision-making process. Children do not become less vulnerable in a linear fashion over the course of development; Thompson (1992) has argued that vulnerability differs by domain, and not merely developmental status. In other words, the risks and benefits associated with different domains of research risk must be evaluated according to the age of the child, as children of different ages may not be equally vulnerable to certain risks.

As the process of weighing protocol risks with developmental factors can be quite complex, Thompson (1992) has offered a few developmental guidelines. With increasing age, the self-concept becomes more coherent and integrated. Therefore, threats to self-concept become more stressful; however, the range of coping skills increases as well, permitting greater adaptive functioning in the face of adversity. These developments suggest that although participation in some types of psychological research may be more stressful for teens than children, they may also have developed coping resources to adapt. As children grow older, they are increasingly able to infer the attitudes and motives of others and develop a greater understanding of individual rights, which serves to balance their views of authority, thus making them less susceptible to coercion. With increasing age, youth are able to take a greater responsibility for their own participation in research, suggesting that perhaps they should be afforded a greater role in consent procedures and decisions regarding reporting and referring.

Second, developmental knowledge must be used to assist investigators in making decisions outside the original protocol, as when a researcher discovers that a participant is in jeopardy. Consider Judy's case: Her data are based on surveys and interviews, therefore she is not manipulating variables with the potential to harm children. However, she may learn that a child is in jeopardy. Should her reaction vary depending upon the age of the child? Some experimentation and risk is developmentally appropriate for teenagers, but what about fourth and sixth graders? It is imperative that Judy be aware of the developmental literature and use this literature to make decisions. For example, we know that by age 16, 50-60 percent of youth have engaged in sexual intercourse; the exact percentage varies by sex and ethnicity (Hofferth and Hayes, 1987). If a participant substantially younger (e.g., aged 11-13) reports sexual activity, that may signal special needs and difficulties, which Judy must attend to. If Judy believes that the child may need treatment or intervention, how should she decide what to do?

Back to Top

5. Options for Action

At least four options are available to Judy and other researchers confronted with similar decisions about how to handle minor participants in danger: maintaining confidentiality, reporting, directly intervening and referring the participant to outside sources of assistance (Fisher, Higgins, Rau, Kuther and Belanger, in press).

Maintain confidentiality -- take no action.

When scientists discover that participants are in potential jeopardy, a no-action stance is common. This response reflects a concern for confidentiality as well as a commitment to scientific validity, which may be threatened by humanitarian actions (Fisher et al., in press; Fisher 1993). Taking no action is supported by ethical guidelines that stress maintaining confidentiality of information derived from research in order to protect participants' right to privacy (APA, 1992; DHHS, 1991; National Commission, 1979). Sharing information about minor participants with parents may, at times, have adverse consequences, especially if the parents react to the disclosure with punitive measures. In addition, acting to assist the participant may threaten the internal validity of a study and jeopardize the trust and participation of other participants.

This tension between the investigator's commitment to scientifically valid designs and the humanitarian obligation to protect participant welfare has been referred to as the "scientist-citizen dilemma" (Veatch, 1987). It has been argued that the interests of researchers and participants diverge, as researchers seek to produce scientifically generalizable knowledge rather than participants' well-being (Scott-Jones, 1994). Many investigators do not acknowledge a humanitarian obligation to their participants outside the provision of informed consent.

Reporting

Unlike the guidelines articulated by the federal government (DHHS, 1991) or American Psychological Association (1992), the Society for Research in Child Development (SRCD)'s Ethical Standards for Research with Children support taking action when a researcher encounters information suggesting that a minor is in danger:

When, in the course of research, information comes to the investigator's attention that may jeopardize the child's well-being, the investigator has a responsibility to discuss the information with the parents or guardians and with those expert in the field in order that they may arrange the necessary assistance for the child (SRCD, 1993, p. 339).

In applied research contexts such as Judy's case, where information suggests delinquent behavior, substance abuse or sexual promiscuity on the part of minors, SRCD's professional guidelines (1993) could be interpreted as encouraging Judy to report the problem to adults who could assist the youths. (Fisher et al., in press) In some cases, the investigator's obligation to protect the immediate welfare of participants may outweigh his or her obligation to produce scientifically valid results, thus supporting the reporting of information obtained in research. In addition, federal, state and local laws must be considered in weighing the decision to report information obtained in research, especially in the case of child abuse, where researchers may be mandated reporters. (See Liss, 1994.)

The decision to report information obtained in research must be carefully considered, especially if error is possible. Reporting may have a negative impact upon the youth and his or her family. For example, child abuse carries a negative social stigma and legal consequences (Scott-Jones, 1994). Investigators must recognize that reporting and referring practices may be affected by their own assumptions about participants, especially if participants are members of vulnerable populations, such as low-income minority youth. In fact, increased surveillance rather than a higher rate of occurrence may promote greater reporting in groups considered to be of low status (e.g., low income, minority and single parent families; Scott-Jones, 1994). Without carefully considering the evidence and potential consequences of reporting information, researchers are in danger of over-reporting suspected problems.

Investigator competence is at the forefront of issues to consider in decisions about whether to report research-derived information. In many cases, investigators are trained in research methodology and may not be clinically trained or equipped to assess the extent of participant problems such as child abuse, substance abuse and depression, or to determine whether treatment is necessary. Although the scientists may recognize that their opinions must be taken with the proverbial grain of salt, as they are not clinicians, their reports are likely to be taken quite seriously (Scott-Jones, 1994). Therefore, they should exercise restraint in reporting suspected problems, and in fact, SRCD's ethical principles recognize this danger: "Because the investigator's words many carry unintended weight with parents and children, caution should be exercised on reporting results, making evaluative statements, or giving advice" (SCRD, 1993, p. 339).

In addition, reporting can violate confidentiality, which has long been regarded as the cornerstone of ethical research. If there is potential for reporting , consent and assent procedures must be modified to include this possibility; the obligation to report changes the nature of informed consent and voluntary participation (Scott-Jones, 1994). For example, if the investigator plans to report abuse, then informed consent and assent require a statement to that effect, so that parents and participants are forewarned. This requirement applies to high risk behavior with minor participants as well.

Intervention

Intervention is an option that may be considered by researchers in Judy's position. In this case, Judy would teach the students coping skills relevant to their particular vulnerabilities. For example, students having difficulties with violence would learn skills such as anger management and conflict mediation. There are two problems with this option: 1) This intervention is not appropriate for every problem encountered (e.g., what skills would be taught in cases of sexual promiscuity?); and 2) intervention would create a dual relationship between Judy and the participants. The ethical guidelines of the American Psychological Association (1992) suggest that professionals refrain from entering into multiple relationships, which may impede objectivity and interfere with a professional's duty. If she intervened, Judy would be entering into a therapeutic relationship with her participants, perhaps creating conflicting roles.

Referral

Referrals may be appropriate in cases where an investigator obtains information suggesting that an adolescent research participant would benefit from medical, social or psychological services, but not from the reporting of the risk status to parents or guardians (Fisher et al., in press). The provision of referral information is an attempt to balance the teen's right to confidentiality with his or her need for treatment. In school-based research, students may be referred to sources within the school, such as the school psychologist or counselor, without violating promises to parents, as these sources of assistance are available to all who attend the school. Provision of a blanket referral could be standard procedure in school-based research; for example, all participants could be provided with a list of local sources of help for common problems such as anxiety, substance abuse and risk of pregnancy. Referral information could be provided for services that adolescents can obtain in normal circumstances without parental consent (i.e., contraception and family planning at a local clinic). However, the provision of referral information is sometimes not enough to protect the participant; the researcher's obligations may be extended depending upon the law, the situation at hand and what the he or she deems appropriate.

Back to Top

6. What should Judy do?

Should Judy suspect that an adolescent research participant is having difficulties, she should first consider whether the difficulties are within the range of normative developmental phenomena for the participant's age. In addition, she should interview the youth to see whether concern is warranted. This step is especially important when the information is derived from survey techniques such as depression, anxiety or risk questionnaire inventories. Such indices usually offer a cut-off score to indicate risk. High scores are indicative of risk, but they are not proof, as identification is not perfect (Brooks-Gunn and Rotheram-Borus, 1994). Because the teen has provided assent and the parent consent, Judy should contact the teen directly to determine whether her suspicions have merit.

If Judy's suspicions are confirmed, the teen must be referred for clinical services. Depending upon the problem, that may or may not require disclosure to parents and their consent. Disclosure to parents violates confidentiality, but failure to provide clinical intervention may not be in the child's best interests (Brooks-Gunn and Rotheram-Borus, 1994). For example, a referral without parental disclosure would be appropriate when services are available to teens without parental permission. For example, referral would be appropriate when a teen has a sexually transmitted disease and can obtain services from a local clinic, unless the teen is engaging in abnormally early sexual activity. However, if a teen has a serious or life-threatening problem such as HIV, the parents must be notified regardless of the participant's wishes. Here, the researcher must assist the youth in obtaining treatment because early treatment increases the length of life and must disclose the information to parents in order to facilitate the pursuit of treatment, which is expensive and often requires hospitalization (Brooks-Gunn and Rotheram-Borus, 1994).

Ideally, the researcher should anticipate the need for treatment or intervention and should make provisions for reporting and referring in the initial protocol. In the consent/assent forms, Judy could have included a statement explaining the possibility of discussing any medical or psychological condition with a parent. If such a statement was not included in the consent/assent form, as in Judy's case, then the researcher must discuss the problem and potential solutions with the teen, as well as the advisability of discussing the problem with parents. The investigator is responsible for working with the participant on a plan for seeking treatment. Depending upon the problem, if the teen refuses to tell his or her parents, the researcher must disclose out of her clinical responsibility to ensure participant welfare, unless there is reason to believe that the parent would not act in the teen's best interest.

Other strategies for protecting participants' privacy could be implemented at the assent or data collection stages. For example, the consent form could include a statement that if problems are identified the researcher would contact the teen and discuss it further (Brooks-Gunn and Rotheram-Borus, 1994). At this time, blanket referrals could be made, providing the participant with information about a variety of available services, as indicated earlier. Another possibility is to ask participants directly, during data collection, if they want to talk with someone about a particular problem or current issue (Brooks-Gunn and Rotheram-Borus, 1994). Participants can be informed that parents will not be told of this desire, and then can be referred to resources within the school such as the school counselor or psychologist, who is better equipped to make decisions about the students' welfare. Finally, should a researcher make a decision that is not in the initial protocol, he or she must seek approval from the institutional review board before taking action.

Back to Top

References

  • American Psychological Association. "Ethical Principles of Psychologists and Code of Conduct." American Psychologist 47 (1992): 1597-1611.
  • Brooks-Gunn, J., and Rotheram-Borus, M. J. "Rights to Privacy in Research: Adolescents versus Parents." Ethics and Behavior 4 (2; 1994): 109-121.
  • Department of Health and Human Services (1991). "Protection of Human Subjects." Code of Federal Regulations, Title 45, Part 46, revised 1991.
  • Fisher, C. B. "Integrating Science and Ethics in Research with High-risk Children and Youth." Society for Research in Child Development: Social Policy Report 7 (4, Winter 1993): 1-26.
  • Fisher, C. B.; Higgins, A.; Rau, J. M. B.; Kuther, T. L.; and Belanger, S. "Reporting and Referring Research Participants at Risk: Views from Urban Adolescents." Child Development (in press).
  • Gisso, T. and Vierling, L. "Minors' Consent to Treatment: A Developmental Perspective." Professional Psychology 9 (1978): 412-427.
  • Hufferth, S. L., and Hayes, C. D. Risking the Future: Adolescent Sexuality, Pregnancy and Child-bearing. Washington, D. C.: National Academy Press, 1987.
  • Liss, M. B. (1994). "Child Abuse: Is There a Mandate for Researchers to Report?" Ethics and Behavior 4 (2, 1994): 133-146.
  • National Commission for the Protection of Human Subjects of Biomedical and Behavioral Research. "The Belmont Report: Ethical Principles and Guidelines for the Protection of Human Subjects Research." Washington, D. C.: Government Printing Office., 1979.
  • Nuremberg Code. Journal of the American Medical Association 132 (1949): 1090.
  • Scott-Jones, D. "Ethical Issues in Reporting and Referring in Research with Low-income Minority Children." Ethics and Behavior 4 (2, 1994): 97-108.
  • Society for Research in Child Development. "Ethical Standards for Research with Children." In Directory of Members. Ann Arbor: Society for Research in Child Development, 1993, pp. 337-339.
  • Thompson, R. A. "Developmental Changes in Research Risk and Benefit: A Changing Calculus of Concerns." In B. Stanley and J. E. Sieber , eds. Social Research on Children and Adolescents: Ethical Issues. Newbury Park, Calif.: Sage, 1992, pp. 31-64.
  • Tymchuk, A. J. "Assent Processes." In B. Stanley and J. E. Sieber, eds. Social Research on Children and Adolescents: Ethical Issues. Newbury Park, Calif.: Sage, 1992, pp. 109-127.
  • Veatch, R. M. The Patient as Partner. Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 1987.
  • Weithorn, L. "Children's Capacities to Decide to Participate in Research." IRB: A Review of Human Subjects Research 5 (2, 1983): 1-5.
  • Weithorn, L. A., and Campbell, S. B. "The Competency of Children and Adolescents to Make Informed Treatment Decisions." Child Development 53 (1982): 1589-159.

Back to Top