Bypassing the IRB

Description

When a graduate student in psychology proposes a novel approach for conducting an experiment for his dissertation, he decides that he does not have time to submit his proposal to his university's institutional review board before he needs to get the pilot experiment finished. This case explores when experiments need IRB approval. 

Body

Part 1

Joshua, a third-year graduate student in psychology, studies decision making. He has devised an experiment for his dissertation. Although the method he plans to employ is commonly used in his field, he will be the first member of his lab to do so. He needs to convince his dissertation committee that it is an appropriate method for the study. The task is a hypothetical gambling task in which participants’ play a card game with losses and gains associated with certain cards. Playing styles are thought to be associated with personality traits such as dis-inhibition and risk seeking. Participants do not play for money; they play for points.

Joshua is meeting with his dissertation committee in one week to propose the study. Although he thinks the methodology has real advantages, he is concerned about proposing a technique that is new to his lab. He knows his dissertation committee would be more open to the idea if he had promising pilot data to submit. As luck would have it, a health fair is scheduled for the weekend. He decides to sign up for a booth and ask attendees to complete his experiment on a laptop. He plans to give them a university bumper sticker as a token thank you gift for their participation. Health fair attendees will provide the pilot data he needs to evaluate the methodology, and all in time for his committee meeting. However, he does not have enough time to submit a proposal to the Institutional Review Board and wait for their decision. When a friend asks about his decision to bypass the board, he explains: “Well, I don’t plan to publish this pilot data so I don’t need approval. Besides, the experiment is relatively innocuous. There doesn’t seem to be much risk to the subjects, and my gift is too small to be coercive.”

Questions

  1. Is this an experiment that needs to go before an IRB for approval? If not, might submission be nonetheless desirable?
  2. Should the experimenter ever be the sole person to make this sort of decision?
  3. In this case, does Joshua have responsibilities beyond the institutional/IRB requirements? How should responsible research be defined? Is it defined solely by institutional requirements or might the underlying ethical considerations apply even if the IRB need not have an official role?

Part 2

After his friend expresses doubts about Joshua’s reasoning, he decides to consult with Dr. Johanson, a member of his committee. Dr. Johanson is very excited about the gambling task and believes that the rest of the committee will be swayed if Joshua presents new data. After thinking about it, Dr. Johanson tells him that he has had “a lot of experience with IRB decisions, and this experiment seems fine. There is no need to submit in my opinion.”

Questions

  1. Can Joshua take this as a green light to proceed? Does the consultation represent adequate peer review? Does the consultation fulfill his ethical responsibilities?
  2. What if a senior investigator has repeated experience with the decisions of the IRB? Can he make decisions for himself and his graduate students about the risks of an experiment? What would be the benefits and risks of such a system of review? 

Part 3

Joshua also speaks with a senior graduate student who teaches the department’s research methods course. She tells him that she requires her undergraduate students to develop and conduct small experiments, and that these experiments implemented for didactic purposes do not need IRB approval. She reasons that Joshua’s pilot study will be conducted for a similar didactic purpose (graduate student training) and therefore falls into the same rubric for exempt research.

Questions

  1. Is the senior graduate student’s argument complete? Does it overlook any important issues?
  2. Where is the line that divides “student research” from research conducted to contribute to “generalizable knowledge”?
Citation
. . Bypassing the IRB. Online Ethics Center. DOI:. https://onlineethics.org/cases/graduate-research-ethics-cases-and-commentaries-volume-7-2006/bypassing-irb.

This case presents a great example of a scenario that reflects the kinds of the experiences and questions that face many researchers while they plan their studies and consider the requirements for oversight by their Institutional Review Board (IRB). The case directly addresses the question of “when is IRB oversight necessary?” The cases highlights how research progress might be given priority over regulatory and ethical issues, how pressure to proceed with research may cloud one’s judgment when considering regulatory and ethical issues, how researchers may misunderstand what the regulations (45 CFR 46) mean by the term, “research,” how researchers may not fully appreciate the role of “pilot data” in the development of knowledge, and how researchers tend to put more weight on the ethical issue of beneficence and the question of risk and fail to consider the central role for the ethical principle of respect for persons.

The case describes a situation where Joshua, who appears to be an enthusiastic and well-motivated graduate student in Psychology, is about to defend his dissertation proposal in a week, but he is concerned that he does not have enough data to convince his dissertation committee of the value of his proposed method of assessing decision-making, which is new to his laboratory. He decides that the best solution is to collect some pilot data using this new method. He apparently realizes that he might need IRB review and approval for this pilot data collection, but he decides that, since he is not planning on publishing these data, he does not need IRB review and approval. He also explains to a friend that the experiment is relatively innocuous, there is not much risk involved, and the payment is too small to be coercive. Being somewhat concerned, Joshua consults with a committee member, Dr. Johanson, who is apparently enthusiastic about the new method. Dr. Johanson assures Joshua that there is no need to have the IRB review and approve the study. Finally, another graduate student likens Joshua’s experiment to didactic student projects in her research methods courses that do not need IRB oversight.

First, this case highlights how research progress can, and often is, given priority over regulatory and ethical issues. Although not explicitly stated in the case, one would imagine that Joshua, with the help of his research advisor, has been planning and working on the proposal for his dissertation project for quite some time, perhaps months. Yet, only at the last minute does he consider the ethical and regulatory issues that might affect his plans. He clearly has given a higher priority to the actual research than to the ethical or regulatory issues. In order to develop his dissertation proposal, Joshua is likely to have spent a lot of time reading the literature, conducting earlier studies, and conferring with his mentor. Apparently, he has not thought of the ethical and regulatory issues until the last minute. In fact, it would appear that the lack of time is a key factor that is affecting his decision-making regarding whether to have the IRB review his pilot project. He appears to be looking for reasons not to submit his project to the IRB, rather than carefully considering the issues and whether his project really should be reviewed by the IRB. This illustrates that Joshua is not taking seriously his responsibility as a researcher to carefully consider the ethical and regulatory issues in research with human participants, and his responsibility as a member of his university to follow university policy regarding the necessity of having all research involving human subjects reviewed by the IRB.

Second, the case illustrates how pressure to proceed with research may cloud one’s judgment when considering regulatory and ethical issues. The case suggests that Joshua’s primary motive is to get some data for the proposal defense, rather than to consider carefully the issues. Joshua appears to be looking for excuses by saying that he does not plan to publish these data and that there is no risk involved. Both of these explanations are fallible. First, as noted below, whether or not one plans on publishing something is not the universal definition of what is meant by “research” by the regulations. This issue is explained in more detail below, but the key to the definition of research is whether the research activity (experiment, study, etc.) is designed to develop or contribute to generalizable knowledge. Pilot data can and often does contribute to generalizable knowledge. Second, just because a project apparently does not carry appreciable risk to participants does not then mean that it does not need to be reviewed by an IRB. There are other ethical principles, such as respect for persons, legal issues, and responsibilities to one’s institution that need to be attended to. Joshua’s judgment appears to be clouded by his apparent conflict of interest between his primary goal of getting his proposal defended and his responsibilities regarding IRB approval. The same can be said of Dr. Johanson, whose reasons for side stepping the IRB process are even more egregious. To say that you know what the IRB would decide and that the experiment seems fine as a rationale for not having a study reviewed is essentially telling the student that you are going to replace the IRB for this decision. Such a response is unethical and represents a clear conflict of interest and lack of understanding the reasons that universities have IRBs in the first place.

Third, this case illustrates how researchers may misunderstand what the regulations (45 CFR 46) mean by the term, “research,” and how researchers may not fully appreciate the role of “pilot data” in the development of knowledge. Research as defined by 45 CFR 46 and articulated by the Indiana University IRB means “a systematic investigation, including research development, testing and evaluation, designed to develop or contribute to generalizable knowledge. Not all data gathering or experimentation is necessarily research; it could be education or therapy. The difference is one of intent or primary goal.” 

Some people operationalize the definition of research to say that any study constitutes research when it is possible that you will publish the data in a scholarly journal, or publish on the web for the same reasons as one would publish in a scholarly journal, or present the data to other researchers at a professional meeting, conference, seminar, or symposium. Whether or not the data is published is only part of that limited definition. Furthermore, pilot data often finds its way into dissertations and presentations at different meetings. In addition, even if one concludes at one point that the data will not ever be published or presented at a meeting, what happens if the data turn out to be far more interesting that one anticipated and one changes one’s mind about publishing and presenting? What does one do then? IRB approval cannot be given to a study that already has been completed. Finally, by its nature the purpose of pilot data is to inform scientifically the researcher about specific aspects of the experimental procedures. In many cases, such data contribute in important ways to the overall knowledge gained through the development of the experimental procedures. To say that the pilot data are not part of the actual study is often inaccurate. Along this line of reasoning, the pilot data that Joshua wants to collect is not at all the same as undergraduate didactic research training projects that are typically conducted in research methods courses. The purpose of the latter is to teach students how to do research; the purpose of the former is to provide data that will inform scientific progress. These are entirely different activities with clearly different intents.

Fourth, this case also illustrates how researchers tend to put more weight on the ethical issue of beneficence and the question of risk and fail to thoroughly consider the central role for the ethical principle of respect for persons. Joshua explains that the study is innocuous and there apparently is no real risk, which he considers as justification for bypassing the IRB. While it may be true that the experiment does not involve more than minimal risk, there is absolutely no consideration of the ethical issue of respect for persons, which involves a consideration of informed consent, how informed consent is achieved and how subjects are recruited such that they are not subject to any undue influence. The case does not discuss exactly how Joshua will attract participants at the health fair, what he will say to them, or whether he has them sign an informed consent statement, so it is unclear whether he has considered these issues. Nonetheless, the case suggests that these issues are not as important to Joshua, or to Dr. Johanson, as they should be.

Finally, the case illustrates the value of having a third party provide input when making ethical decisions about one’s own research. Researchers can become so wrapped up in their research, or so driven by their enthusiasm for their research, that they might not have the objectivity necessary to make ethical and legal judgments about their own work. Both Joshua and Dr. Johanson were so focused on the desire to get on with the research, that they missed very important issues and responsibilities regarding oversight by the IRB.

This case raises issues of the role of the IRB and the relationship between this ethical governance board and the individual researcher. Initially some issues raised by the case may seem ethically blurred. However, this is a case in which the researcher has a clear and well- established responsibility to submit a human subject’s research proposal to formalized, peer oversight.

The National Research Act, Public Law 93-348, requires that any institution conducting research that involves human participants establish an Institutional Review Board. All proposals for research involving human participants must be submitted to this board, which is charged with determining the legality of the research, and more importantly, compliance with higher ethical standards. The jurisdiction of the board extends to all research conducted to add to “generalizable knowledge.” These boards have ultimate authority over what research can and cannot be conducted at an institution. Research that has not yet been approved (or more obviously, been rejected by the board) cannot be pursued.  The question of what constitutes “research conducted to add to generalizable knowledge” and hence, what forms of research obligate a researcher to submit to board oversight is perhaps best answered in the negative. That is, what kind of “research” falls outside the jurisdiction of the Institutional Review Board? (See Title 45 CFR Part 46.101 for complete exemptions)  Pilot testing is one form that may not require formal oversight. In many cases, pilot testing of a new method or measure is first conducted with a small number of people. Often these pilot participants are members of the laboratory, graduate students, or a few of the researchers close friends. These pilot tests, of extremely limited scope, with little risk, and participants who are often also formally involved in the research, are typically exempt from IRB oversight. Note that this exemption is quite narrow. It does not include research with any possibility of risk or “pilot” research that includes participants with little connection to the laboratory. Given the limited nature of the exemption, it may be prudent for researchers to check informally with their IRB before deciding to proceed without board oversight.

Second, data collected solely for administrative purposes are not subject to IRB oversight. For example, university Registrar offices maintain large databases of student academic records. These data are employed to track student and university progress, but are not systematically collected to answer scientific research questions. For this reason, university administrators are not required to submit their tracking system (or similar databases) to the IRB for approval.

Finally, research that is conducted in the classroom for didactic purposes is also considered exempt. For example, a professor teaching a statistics course might collect a small data set from his students in order to illustrate a statistical technique (for example, the physical height of men and women in the class). The data are clearly not collected to add to scientific knowledge and carry no potential for harm. As such, it would be unwieldy and excessive to ask this professor to submit a proposal and wait for formal approval (not to mention, a waste of time for the reviewers).  This exemption is slightly less clear in the case of student led research. For example, research methods courses in psychology and sociology often involve a component in which each student (or groups of students) conducts a small study in order to provide hands-on experience with research design, data collection and statistical analysis. Typically, the student’s classmates serve as the research participants. This student research is technically exempt. However, the instructor should be sensitive to ethical considerations and ensure that student research meets the same standards required of research intended to add to scientific knowledge.

It is a common misconception that research not intended to be published is also an exempt category. It is sometimes mistakenly believed that the “generalizable knowledge” clause refers only to research that is published in scientific journals. In fact, the clause should be interpreted more broadly.  For example, a graduate student who conducts a small study and who plans to present this data at a departmental colloquium, but not to publish, is indeed adding to generalizable knowledge. The study was conducted to answer a research question and the obtained answer was shared with a small group of the research community. Extensive pilot testing, whether or not it is published, is also not exempt. Data obtained from these pilots contributes to the researchers understanding of the research question and even if not directly published, informs the direction of future published research. Lack of intent to publish is not considered a legitimate reason to bypass the oversight of an ethics board. Human participants have the right to be protected by independent ethical oversight whether or not the data they contribute is ultimately printed on the published page.

The study that Joshua plans to conduct does not meet requirements for exempt research. Although the study is a “pilot” study, the use of community participants moves this proposal outside the confines of typical pilot work and must be considered by an IRB like all other research. There may be a temptation for researchers to do the work of the IRB themselves. This is illustrated by Joshua’s argument about the non-coercive nature of the gift and the limited risk of the project. However, researchers have a vested interest in the process and may not be capable of making an unbiased decision about the risks involved in their research. For example, Joshua does not seem to consider the risk the experiment may pose to individuals with gambling problems. IRB members may have noticed this risk and been able to work with Joshua to mitigate it. By pursuing his research without the input of the IRB, he lost this valuable insight.  Joshua’s committee member, Dr. Johanson, also demonstrates the temptation of researchers to predict the ruling of the IRB.  In addition, he provides a poor example to a graduate student. His behavior indicates to Joshua that IRBs and ethics are not primary concerns in psychological research.

Finally, the graduate student who counsels Joshua that research conducted for didactic purposes is exempt from IRB approval is correct in this point. However she is incorrect to stretch the exclusion to cover Joshua’s research. While it is true that graduate training is a learning process, it also produces (and is intended to produce) empirical findings with implications outside of the classroom. As such, the fact that the research was conducted during graduate school does not constitute a broad exemption from ethical oversight. In fact, part of graduate training ought to be in research ethics and in the applied skills of communicating with an IRB.  

This case study includes many of the arguments hurried or frustrated researchers may use to justify bypassing the oversight of an ethics board. When deadlines approach it may be particularly tempting to find ways to avoid an extra step in the research process. However, all researchers who employ human subjects should be grateful for the donation that participants make to scientific knowledge and should repay this debt with a genuine consideration of their welfare. Submitting research proposals to the IRB is only one way, but an extremely important way, to ensure that subjects are protected.

Reference

Title 45 CFR Part 46.101.